RESEARCH ARTICLE
The vicarious liability of sports governing bodies and
competition organisers
James Brown*
Manchester Metropolitan University, Manchester, UK
*Author email: [email protected]c.uk
(Accepted 31 August 2022)
Abstract
This is the first work to explore the possibility of holding sports governing bodies and competition
organisers vicariously liable for the tortious behaviour of athletes that compete under their auspices. In
contrast to other scholarly contributions on vicarious liability in sport, this paper examines the scope
of responsibility for athletes in individual sports (as opposed to team sports). It begins by drawing
upon the recent tribunal proceedings between professional cyclist Jess Varnish and British Cycling to
analyse the employment status of government-funded individual athletes. In calling for a contextual
and policy-sensitive approach to the definition of an employee, this paper argues that certain normative
and theoretical considerations ought to be granted more or less weight depending on the particular legal
issue animating the dispute. Thereafter, and with one eye on the overly intrusive regulatory provisions
found in sports such as tennis and golf, this paper also demonstrates that the vicarious liability of
governing bodies and competition organisers could equally be extended to cover the tortious conduct
of non-funded individual athletes. In making these claims, it is demonstrated how a sport-specific appli-
cation of the doctrine may help to teach us a few broader lessons about vicarious liability more generally.
Keywords: tort law; vicarious liability; sports law; employment law; sporting regulation
Introduction
The doctrine of vicarious liability has long been recognised as a fundamental aspect of tort law. It
stands for the proposition that one party will be strictly liable for the harmful conduct of another,
so long as there is a close connection between the injury and the wrongdoers relationship with the
defendant. It is most commonly used to hold employers responsible for the actions of their employees,
although recent case law has established that vicarious liability may also be imposed for relationships
that are merely akin to employment.
1
This development was seemingly intertwined with a judicial appreciation of the various theoretical
rationales for vicarious liability. As evidenced by Lord Phillips five-factor test in Various Claimants v
Catholic Child Welfare Society,
2
several justifications for the doctrine can be identified. These include,
for instance: loss spreading and deep pockets (which suggest that liability ought to be imposed on the
party who is best able to financially bear the loss); control (which maintains that employers are usually
I would like to thank Professor Tsachi Keren-Paz, Dr Andreas Rühmkorf and the two anonymous reviewers for their
insightful comments on previous iterations of this paper. A version of this paper was also presented at the Sport and
Recreation Law Association Conference on 23 February 2021. As such, I would also like to thank the organisers and parti-
cipants of this conference for their helpful feedback.
1
JGE v English Province of Our Lady of Charity [2013] QB 722.
2
[2012] UKSC 56 at [35].
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Society of Legal Scholars. This is an Open Access article,
distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unre-
stricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Legal Studies (2023), 43, 221239
doi:10.1017/lst.2022.34
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
in the best position to prevent the harm); risk (which highlights that employers ought to be held
responsible for any inherent or foreseeable harm that flows from their enterprise); and fairness
(which indicates that those who seek to benefit from a particular activity should also be held account-
able for any losses that such activity causes). The final two justifications might be said to be two over-
lapping formulations of the wider concept of enterprise liability.
3
The argument propounded in this paper is that an application of these theories justifies the imposition of
vicarious liability on national governing bodies (NGBs) and competition organisers for the tortious behav-
iour of athletes in so-called individual sports (such as tennis, boxing and golf). Of course, one might suggest
that such an e xamination of theory is erroneous follo wing the recent case of Barclay s Bank v Various
Claimants. There, Lady Hale relega ted the use of theory to all but the most doubtful of cases, and she sug-
gested in line with the judgment in WM Morrison Supermarkets plc v Various Claimants
4
that we ought
to adopt a more principled, incremental approach tha t derives assis tance from previously decided cases in
this ar ea of law .
5
However, in contrast to some scholars who have suggested that Barclays may finally
have halted the ever-growing expansion of vicarious liability,
6
I am somewha t sceptical as to whether the
Supreme Courts judgment in Barcla ys has had the desired effect. After all, the various possible interpr eta-
tions of the term doubtful indicate that theory could, in fa ct, continue to play a significant r ole in future
vicarious liability cases. In this r egard, it is notable that, following Barclay s, we see barristers regularly sub-
mitting (and judges subsequently accepting) tha t a particular case is doubtful,
7
and many judges also still
seem keen to continue referring to Lord Phillips five-factor test when jus tifying their conclusions.
8
Moreover,oneperhapsonlyneedstobrieflyperusetheexistingworkonsportingvicariousliabilityin
order to expre ss some doubt as to whether vicarious liability is applicable to the individual sporting con-
text. Indeed, the exis ting scholarly analysis on sporting vicarious liability has been predominantly , if not
exclusiv ely , directed towards the responsibility of employers in team sports.
9
Whilst Anderson obser v es
that vicarious liability for negligent on-field acts in this context has rea ched an almost presumptive,
uncontested sta tus,
10
there has been an alarming lack of discussion in relation to the appropriate scope
of responsibility for individual athletes. This is also reflected by the fact tha t case law on sporting vicarious
liability in both the UK and overseas has been centr ed entir ely around team sports such as football,
11
rugby union
12
and basketball.
13
3
J Neyers A theory of vicarious liability (2005) 43 Alberta Law Review 287 at 297298.
4
[2020] UKSC 12 at [24] per Lord Reed.
5
[2020] UKSC 13 at [27]. See also P Giliker Can the Supreme Court halt the ongoing expansion of vicarious liability?
Barclays and Morrison in the UK Supreme Court (2021) 37 PN 55 at 66.
6
C Purshouse Halting the vicarious liability juggernaut: Barclays Bank PLC v Various Claimants (2020) 28 Medical Law
Review 794.
7
Hughes v Rattan [2021] EWHC 2032 (QB) at [100] per Collins QC; DJ v Barnsley MBC [2021] 1 WLUK 632 at [23] per
Myerson QC.
8
MXX v A Secondary School [2022] EWHC 2207 (QB) at [200] per HHJ Carmel Wall; TVZ & others v Manchester City
Football Club Ltd [2022] EWHC 7 (QB) at [321] per Johnson J; Blackpool Football Club Ltd v DSN [2021] EWCA Civ 1352 at
[100][104] per Stuart-Smith LJ; JXJ v The Province of Great Britain of the Institute of Brothers of the Christian Schools [2020]
EWHC 1914 (QB) at [144] per Chamberlain J.
9
See eg S Rubin The vicarious liability of professional sports teams for on-the-field assaults committed by their players
(1999) 1 Virginia Journal of Sports & the Law 266; M James and D McArdle Player violence, or violent players? Vicarious
liability for sports participants (2004) 12 Tort Law Review 131; N Parpworth Vicarious liability on the rugby union field
(2008) 172 JP 572; J Harris A sporting chance (2012) 162 New Law Journal 1248; M Beloff et al Sports Law (Oxford: Hart
Publishing, 2nd edn, 2012) pp 157158; P Morgan Vicarious liability and the beautiful game liability for professional and
amateur footballers? (2018) 38 LS 242.
10
J Anderson Modern Sports Law (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2010) p 243.
11
Elliott v Saunders and Liverpool FC (unreported, 10 June 1994) QBD; McCord v Cornforth and Swansea City AFC (1997)
The Times, 11 February; Gaynor v Blackpool Football Club [2002] CLY 3280.
12
Gravil v Carroll and Redruth Rugby Football Club [2008] EWCA Civ 689. In the context of rugby league, see Canterbury
Bankstown Rugby League Football Club v Rogers [1993] Aust Tort Reports 81-246; McCracken v Melbourne Storm Rugby
League Football Club [2005] NSWSC 107.
13
Tomjanovich v California Sports Inc No H-78-243 (SD Tex Aug 17, 1979).
222 James Brown
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Now, it must be appreciated that there is perhaps good reason for this: English law has long recognised
that professional athletes are employees of the clubs they represent.
14
In contrast, the classic position (at
least for the purposes of employment law) has generally remained that athletes in so-called individual
sports are independent contractors working on their own account.
15
The purpose of this paper is to chal-
lenge that assumption by examining, from a theoretical standpoint, how the overly intrusive regulatory pro-
visions of many NGBs and competition organisers could lead to them being held vicariously liable for the
athletes that compete under their auspices. This is both a descriptive and normative argument based on the
first necessary element of any vicarious liability claim: the establishment of a sufficient relationship.
To be clear, ther e is nothing particularly nov e l in claiming that NGBs ought to be held r esponsible for
on-field injury. This is illus tr a t ed by Vowles v Evans and Welsh Rugby Union, a case in which the Welsh
Rugby Union was held vicariously liable for the negligence of one of its appointed refer ees.
16
The point
raised in this paper, ho w ever, is tha t this liability has yet to be extended to cover r esponsibility for the tor-
tious beha viour of athletes. Whilst James notes that the liability of NGBs is the leas t explor ed area of
sports-rela ted personal injury claims,
17
he does highlight that the law on sports torts continues to extend
legal liability to new contexts and ne w defendants who had not previously considered themselv es to be at
risk from litigation.
18
As such, it may only be a matter of time before an inno va tiv e claimant looks to take
advantage of the solvency of a governing body or competition organiser in their pursuit of compensat ion.
With this in mind, it is worth noting that this paper is separated into two (largely overlapping)
parts. The first relates to vicarious liability for government-funded individual athletes. In con tributing
to the growing debate on the relevance of other areas of law to the determination of employment status
for vicarious liability, I draw upon insights from the recent tribunal proceedings between professional
cyclist Jess Varnish and British Cycling to argue for a contextual and policy-sensitive approach to
employer liability. Thereafter, and in the second part of the paper, I examine how the theoretical
and normative rationales for liability in the funded context can equally be transposed to justify vicari-
ous liability for non-funded individual athletes. In this regard, I utilise professional tennis and profes-
sional golf as two instructive examples. In making this argument, I also endeavour to demonstrate how
an application of the doctrine to the individual sporting context may help to teach us some broader
lessons about vicarious liability more generally.
1. Vicarious liability for funded individual athletes
The reference to the funded athlete here refers to those professional sports participants who are
funded by an NGB in order to help them fulfil their athletic and medal-winning potential. With
the assistance of funding from UK Sport, NGBs are able to operate a World Class Performance
Programme (WCPP) in their respective sports.
19
Those athletes selected for a WCPP will enter into
a Performance Athlete Agreement (PAA) which imposes certain obligations on the individual partici-
pant (such as, for example, behavioural standards or restrictions relating to their image rights).
20
In
return, NGBs provide a wide range of benefits including the provision of world-class coaching,
sports science advice and access to high-tech equipment and facilities
21
which are estimated to be
14
Walker v Crystal Palace FC [1910] 1 KB 87 at 93 per Farwell LJ.
15
S Gardiner et al Sports Law (Abingdon: Routledge, 4th edn, 2012) p 396; M Minkowitz Jockeying for benefits pro-
fessional athletes and workers compensation (1991) 21 Brief 24 at 24.
16
[2003] EWCA Civ 318.
17
M James Sports Law (London: Palgrave, 3rd edn, 2017) p 111.
18
Ibid, p 99. See also H Opie Survey: a global perspective on the most important cases affecting the sports industry (2009)
16 Villanova Sports & Entertainment Law Journal 99 at 109 (arguing that civil courts have allowed increasingly exotic claims
in the sports context).
19
See eg, https://www.britishat hletics.org.uk/uk-sport/. This and all other weblinks were last accessed on 8 September 2022.
20
A Smith et al The funding and employment status of elite athletes a comparison of the UK, USA and Germany
LawInSport 6 May 2016, available at https://www.lawinsport.com/topics/item/the-funding-and-employment-status-of-elite-
athletes-a-comparison-of-the-uk-usa-and-germany.
21
See https://www.uksport.gov.uk/our-work/investing-in-sport/how-uk-sport-funding-works.
Legal Studies 223
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
worth up to £60,000 per athlete per annum.
22
Alongside this, UK Sport also directly funds (primarily
through National Lottery income) the living and personal sporting costs of WCPP-initiated athletes
through the guise of an Athlete Performance Award (APA).
23
This is awarded on the basis of both
means-testing and athletic potential, with athletes at the so-called Podium level usually receiving
an annual £28,000 tax-free grant.
24
Around 1,100 of the UKs leading athletes in a variety of individual
sports benefit from such investment,
25
with many participants (such as those in athletics or cycling)
reliant on the funding for much of their professional careers.
26
Unfortunately, and perhaps due to the desire for medals and national success, many NGBs have
adopted a domineering approach over their athletes that might be said to imitate the role of an
employer instructing an employee. Despite protestations in both the UK
27
and USA
28
that the
agreement between an athlete and their respective sporting body only gives rise to independent con-
tractor status, the courts have frequently stressed that they will look to the reality of the situation
rather than simply defer to the label used by the parties themselves.
29
This is a particularly important
exercise for many sports-related employment disputes because, as Schwab highlights,
30
most NGBs
can exert monopolistic power over athletes on a take it or leave it basis,
31
and it is unlikely that
an athlete would be able to compete under the auspices of an NGB without adhering to their legally
controversial contractual demands.
32
Consequently, it is little surprise that some funded athletes have
sought to challenge their legal status as independent contractors. The most relevant case in point here
involves the recent legal proceedings between professional cyclist Jess Varnish and British Cycling/UK
Sport.
(a) Varnish v British Cycling Federation
The crux of this case rested on the true reason for Varnish being dropped from British Cycling s
WCPP in 2016. Whilst the governing body maintained that the decision was performance-related,
Varnish contended that the underlying reason related to both her criticism of certain coaches at
British Cycling, and the misogynistic comme nts of its former technical director, Shane Sutton (who
allegedly told Varnish to go and have a baby).
33
However, before she could pursue a claim for unfair
dismissal or sex discrimination, she first had to prove that she was eith er an employee or worker of
British Cycling or UK Sport under section 230 of the Employment Rights Act 1996. The
22
Smith et al, above n 20.
23
J Taylor and J Herbert Government intervention in the sports sector in A Lewis and J Taylor (eds) Sport: Law and
Practice (Haywards Heath: Bloomsbury, 3rd edn, 2014) p 32.
24
S Ingle Jess Varnish loses employment tribunal against British Cycling and UK Sport The Guardian 16 January 2019,
available at https://www.theguardian.com/sport/2019/jan/16/jess-varnish-employment-tribunal-british-cycling-uk-sport.
25
Ibid. According to https://www.uksport.gov.uk/our-work/investing-in-sport/current-funding-figures, UK Sport funds,
through contributions to the respective NGBs, the following individual sports: archery, athletics, badminton, boxing, canoe-
ing, cycling, diving, equestrian, gymnastics, judo, karate, rowing, sailing, shooting, swimming, taekwondo and triathlon.
26
L Payne and C Mathews The employment status and rights of funded athletes in the UK LawInSport 13 November
2018, available at https://www.lawinsport.com/topics/item/the-employment-status-and-rights-of-funded-athletes-in-the-uk.
27
K Russell and R Nicholson Are professional athletes employees? (2019) 10 GSLTR 36 at 3839 (referring to British
Cyclings statement which suggests that its relationship with [athletes] is not one of employer-employee but that of a service
provider supporting talented and dedicated athletes to achieve their best).
28
Smith et al, above n 20 (highlighting the US Rowing APA which maintains that athletes are independent contractors
providing services to US Rowing on a contract basis).
29
Autoclenz Ltd v Belcher [2011] UKSC 41 at [22].
30
B Schwab Embedding the human rights of players in world sport (2018) 17 International Sports Law Journal 214 at
217218.
31
R v Disciplinary Committee of the Jockey Club, ex p Aga Khan [1993] 1 WLR 909 at 929930 per Farquarhson LJ.
32
Schwab, above n 30, at 217218.
33
PA Media Jess Varnish wins right to appeal against verdict in British Cycling case The Guardian 17 December 2019,
available at https://www.theguardian.com/sport/2019/dec/17/jess-varnish-wins-right-to-appeal-verdict-in-case-against-brit-
ish-cycling.
224 James Brown
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Employment Tribunal (ET) at first instance concluded much like it had done almost 20 years earlier
in relation to a similar claim by former track cyclist Wendy Everson
34
that Varnish was neither an
employee of, nor a worker for, the governing body.
35
Likewise, the absence of any day-to-day relation-
ship between the claimant and UK Sport similarly precluded employee and worker status here.
36
In
her appeal case that dropped the (presumably weaker) claim against UK Sport, the Employment
Appeal Tribunal (EAT) reaffirmed the ET s decision on the basis that the first instance tribunal
had properly and reasonably directed itself as to the relevant legal and factual principles.
37
The key
features of this litigation were the so-called three irreducible minimum requirements needed to
establish an employment relationship: mutuality of obligation; personal performance; and control.
38
Given that Varnish did not challenge the initial judgment on the two latter requirements, it may
reasonably be concluded that Judge Ross sentiments on these two factors in the ET continue to
constitute good law.
On the issue of control, the ET considered this to be a significant feature, in that many aspects of
[Varnishs] life including what she ate how, when and where she trained were closely controlled by
British Cycling.
39
With reference to the PAA, Judge Ross also found that the NGB exercised control
over the claimants media image and appearances, her personal commercial work and use of social
media, and when she could take time off.
40
Interestingly, the ET also found that Varnish was inte-
grated into [British Cyclings] organisation, working closely with her coach and wearing the team
clothing at all events and training sessions.
41
Although not every aspect of the purported employment
relationship between the two parties was supported by the notion of control (such as the fact that
Varnish could choose both her own coach and equipment if she so wished),
42
it was clear that
Judge Ross considered British Cyclings degree of control in this scenario as taking them beyond a
mere regulator of the sport. Unfortunately for Varnish, however, this fact was outweighed by the
absence of mutual obligations and personal service in her relationship with British Cycling.
43
In relation to mutual obligations, Mr Justice Choudhury in the EAT rejected the claimants plea
that the obligations under the PAA constituted work (and that the services simultaneously provided
to her constituted remuneration),
44
and he reiterated the ETs findings that she was simply privy to a
contract where services are provided to [her], not the other way around.
45
In other words, there was
no obligation on British Cycling to provide work, nor was there a corresponding obligation on
Varnishs part to accept and perform the work in exchange for consideration, usually wages.
46
This finding seemingly also influenced the view that Varnish failed to satisfy the personal performance
requirement. On this issue, Judge Ross found that, whilst Varnish certainly could not substitute
another rider to carry out her obligations under the PAA,
47
she was not personally performing
work provided by British Cycling. Rather, she was simply performing a commitment to train in
accordance with the individual rider agreement in the hop e that she would be selected for
34
Everson v British Cycling Federation, case no 2405213/99, 12 June 2001.
35
Miss J Varnish v British Cycling and UK Sport, case no 2404219, 1017 December 2018.
36
Ibid, at [274].
37
Miss J Varnish v British Cycling [2020] UKEAT/0022/20/LA (citing Quashie v Stringfellow Restaurants Ltd [2013] IRLR
99 at [9] per Elias LJ).
38
Ready Mixed Concrete (South East) Ltd v Minister of Pensions and National Insurance [1968] 2 QB 497; Nethermere
(St Neots) Ltd v Gardiner & Another [1984] ICR 612.
39
Varnish, above n 35, at [158][159].
40
Ibid, at [160][163].
41
Ibid, at [224].
42
Ibid, at [230].
43
Ibid, at [154].
44
Varnish, above n 37, at [41].
45
Varnish, above n 35, at [245].
46
Ibid, at [139].
47
As was made clear in Express and Echo Publications Ltd v Tanton [1999] IRLR 367, a contractual term indicating that the
individual may provide a substitute to carry out the work is inconsistent with a contract of employment.
Legal Studies 225
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
international competition.
48
Given that the determination of personal performance here hinged
heavily on the so-called wage/work bargain, one might say that it was the lack of mutual obligations
between the two parties that was fundamental in deciding the employment status of Varnish in this
case.
49
Now, for our purposes, it is interesting to consider what might have happened in the alternative
scenario if Varnish had not been dropped from Team GB in 2016, but instead had gone on to compete
in future professional events whilst funded by British Cycling. Let us say that, during one such event,
she negligently (or intentionally) injured a fellow competitor or spectator, perhaps in a similar manner
to Miguel Angel Lopez when he punched a fan at the Giro dItalia in 2019.
50
If the current decision in
Varnish is also the benchmark for determining an employment relationship in the law of tort, then
British Cycling would clearly not be held vicariously liable for this act. Nevertheless, it must be ques-
tioned whether the definition of an employee might and indeed should differ depending on the
area of law in question. As I explore below, the generally received view now favours a context-specific
approach to the definition of employment. However, there has been very little critical discussion as to
what extent cases from employment law (and indeed other areas of law) might provide an instructive
steer in determining the scope of vicarious liability. The following sections seek to fill in this gap in the
literature, as well as hopefully shedding some light on the relevance of Varnish to the vicarious liability
of NGBs.
(b) Employment law and vicarious liability: time for harmonisation?
Until fairly recently, it had long been assumed that the definition of an employee was the same across
multiple strands of the law (whether that be employment, insurance, intellectual property or tort
law).
51
As testament to this fact, many of the leading monographs and textbooks discussing the neces-
sary relationship for vicarious liability refer interchangeably to labour law cases.
52
However, recent
judicial statements appear to now cast some doubt on this idea. In particular, Lady Hale in
Barclays suggested that whilst it might be tempting to align the law of vicarious liability with employ-
ment law, it would ultimately be going too far down the road to tidiness to do so in light of the dif-
fering contextual reasons in each domain.
53
This appreciation of context-specificity is echoed by Ward
LJs function-over-form approach in JGE v English Province of Our Lady of Charity.
54
As his Lordship
explains:
If the case is one where an employee seeks a remedy against his employer, for example for unfair
dismissal, then the case does require that the true relationship of employer/employee be estab-
lished in order to found the claim On the other hand, the remedy of an innocent victim
48
Varnish, above n 35, at [157], [242].
49
This is also reinforced by the fact that the ETs findings on mutuality of obligation constituted the bulk of Varnishs
appeal in the EAT.
50
L Ostlere Miguel Angel Lopez escapes punishment after punching Giro dItalia fan who knocked him off bike on stage
20 The Independent 1 June 2019, available at https://www.independent.co.uk/sport/cycling/giro-ditalia-2019-miguel-angel-
lopez-punches-fan-video-watch-crash-a8939806.html.
51
P Case Developments in vicarious liability: shifting sands and slippery slopes (2006) 22 PN 161 at 164; P Atiyah
Vicarious Liability in the Law of Torts (London: Butterworths, 1967) pp 3133; A Stewart Redefining employment?
Meeting the challenge of contract and agency labour (2002) 15 Australian Journal of Labour Law 235.
52
See eg, A Gray Vicarious Liability: Critique and Reform (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2018) ch 9; N McBride and R Bagshaw
Tort Law (London: Pearson, 6th edn, 2018) ch 31; M Lunney et al Tort Law: Text and Materials (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 6th edn, 2017) ch 15; S Deakin and Z Adams Markesinis and Deakins Tort Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 8th
edn, 2019) ch 19.
53
Barclays, above n 5, at [29].
54
JGE, above n 1. See also Jones v Tower Boot Co [1997] 2 All ER 395 (the term course of employment here was, in the
context of the Race Relations Act 1976, given a wider meaning than it currently possesses under the common law of vicarious
liability).
226 James Brown
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
against the employer of the wrongdoer has a different justification rooted, as we have seen, in
public policy. The fluid concept of vicarious liability should not, therefore, be confined by the
concrete demands of statutory construction arising in a wholly different context.
55
Now, it is worth highlighting that not every employment law scholar has subscribed to this viewpoint.
Butlin and Allen, for instance, are perhaps the most prominent advocates of a harmonising approach
to the employment relationship, and they suggest that the law on vicarious liability and worker status
should march hand in hand because they are inextricably interlinked.
56
In this, they promote a con-
flation of the employment and vicarious liability contexts in order to avoid a damaging and undesir-
able risk of regulatory dissonance,
57
as well as to ensure legal certainty for both employers and
employees across different strands of the law.
58
Pitt adopts a similar view, arguing that it would be
undesirable if different tests were to develop for identifying contracts of employment according to
what was at stake.
59
One of the key tenets of this view is that it helps to ensure consistency between
two interwoven strands of the law.
60
However, if, as I suspect, the policies at play are oftentimes dif-
ferent in both the employment and vicarious liability contexts, then a lack of consistency between
them becomes not just unproblematic, but also perhaps sometimes desirable. As I explore shortly,
the notion of victim compensation is one policy goal that is arguably more pressing in the context
of vicarious liability than it is in the context of employment law.
For such reasons, I find Butlin and Allens view unconvincing, and this can perhaps be best illu-
strated by considering the mutuality of obligation requirement in both employment and tort law. More
specifically, whilst the concept of mutual obligations has been described as the most prominent
61
and
essential
62
feature of contemporary employment protection litigation, it is, I suggest, a largely irrele-
vant factor in the determination of an employers strict liability for the torts of their employees. As
Kidner opines, an analysis of the mutuality requirement is likely to skew our view of the employer-
employee relationship towards the demands of employment law and the policies embedded therein.
63
In fact, the most recent judgment of the EAT in Varnish suggests an even more contextualised role for
mutuality of obligation, with Mr Justice Choudhury highlighting that it may only be a useful criterion
in employment law for cases involving intermittent working environments.
64
As such, it is suggested
that the theory of control is a much more apt consideration for vicarious liability cases, and it should
certainly not be viewed as possessing the same importance in this context as the concept of mutuality
or other employment law-specific considerations (such as whether an individual is treated as an
employee for tax purposes). This is so for two reasons.
First, it must be recognised that the concept of mutuality focusses solely on the relationship
between the purported employer and employee. In contrast, and as Ward LJ in JGE referred to
above, vicarious liability cases possess an added component: an innocent third-party victim. In this
regard, the theory of control appears to be a far more useful factor to consider. Whilst it is true
that the control is exercised by the employer over the employee, the existence or absence of such con-
trol has an important moral and normative impact on third parties. Three particular cases illustrate
this point well.
55
Ibid, at [59].
56
S Butlin and R Allen Worker status and vicarious liability: the need for coherence (2018) (University of Cambridge
Faculty of Law Research Paper No 21/2018) at 2.
57
Ibid.
58
Ibid, at 1.
59
G Pitt Employment Law (London: Sweet and Maxwell, 9th edn, 2014) pp 102103.
60
Butlin and Allen, above n 56, at 11.
61
J Prassl The Concept of the Employer (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015) p 30.
62
Nethermere, above n 38, at 632 per Dillion LJ.
63
R Kidner Vicarious liability: for whom should the employer be liable? (1995) 15 LS 47 at 47.
64
Varnish, above n 37, at [39].
Legal Studies 227
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
The first is that of Home Office v Dorset Yacht Co Ltd,
65
a case in which the government were held
liable in negligence for a failure to control the actions of several borstal boys. Whilst it is clear that the
context of the proceedings was different in this case (the claimants preferring instead to base their
claim on primary liability grounds),
66
Dorset Yacht is still of great importance in highlighting that
control imports responsibility when assessing the liability of a defendant for the actions of another.
67
Such comments also provide us with a useful framework for examining the relationship between
employment law and vicarious liability: decisions in the former should only be instructive for the latter
when the focus is on those cases, or parts of cases, which share the same underlying policies. Whilst
Dorset Yacht indicates that control is one such policy that straddles both areas of law, mutuality of
obligations does not. Likewise, deep pockets and loss spreading are fine examples of theories that
are important for vicarious liability, but not particularly relevant for employment law purposes.
The fact that many individual athletes (such as Varnish) are required to apply for funding may indi-
cate that such athletes do not possess deep pockets, at least not vis-à-vis their NGB. However, whilst
such an analysis is relevant for vicarious liability purposes, it is of far less normative importance in the
employment context when dec iding whether an individual was unfairly dismissed.
This argument can be sharpened by taking a second example from the facts of OKelly v Trusthouse
Forte.
68
In this case, a hotel employed wine butlers on a regular yet casual basis, such that the hotel
was not obliged to provide (and the staff were not obliged to accept) any work. When one of the but-
lers was fired, his claim for unfair dismissal was rejected by the Court of Appeal on the basis that his
relationship with the hotel lacked the necessary mutuality of obligation. However, once we drop the
unnecessary baggage of additional employment law provisions such as the need for mutuality,
69
we can see how a vicarious liability claim might have succeeded on the facts of OKelly. As Kidner
posits, in light of the divergence of the needs of employment law and vicarious liability, it would
be entirely surprising if the hotel was not vicariously liable for one of their casual waiters negligently
spilling wine over a patron.
70
It is likely that Peel and Goudkamp also had this case in mind when they
correctly argued that there is something distinctly odd about a scenario whereby an employer exhibits
close control over a tortfeasors manner of work, yet the employer is not held liable for the tortfeasors
acts simply because they had the option to dec line him work at certain times.
71
With this in mind,
I can do little more than to echo McKendricks view that the test for the existence of an employment
relationship should depend upon the legal question which is being asked.
72
In this light, we perhaps
ought to treat cases such as Kafagi v JBW Group Ltd which refer indiscriminately to purely employ-
ment law policies such as mutuality of obligation in determining the scope of vicarious liability
73
with a degree of caution.
A third and final case law example illustrating the different policies at play in employment and tort
law can be found in Sedley LJs judgment in Dacas v Brook Street Bureau (UK) Ltd.
74
Whilst the
employment tribunal in these proceedings had previously concluded that no employment relationship
existed between the claimant and Wandsworth Council for the purposes of an unfair dismissal claim,
65
[1970] AC 1004.
66
cf J Gardner What is tort law for? Part 1: the place of corrective justice (2011) 30 Law & Phil 1 at 19 (arguing that
Dorset Yacht should have been treated as a vicarious liability case).
67
Dorset Yacht, above n 65, at 1055 per Lord Pearson. See also Kafagi v JBW Group [2018] EWCA Civ 1157 at [41] per
Singh LJ.
68
[1984] 1 QB 90.
69
P Morgan Vicarious liability for group companies: the final frontier of vicarious liability? (2015) 31 PN 276 at 295.
70
Kidner, above n 63, at 50. As he further elaborates (at 49), the mutuality of obligation argument, while highly significant
for employment law, may not prove too damaging for vicarious liability since it can be argued that when the waiters presented
themselves for and began work there was a binding obligation on both sides.
71
E Peel and J Goudkamp Winfield and Jolowicz on Tort (London: Sweet and Maxwell, 19th edn, 2014) para [21-011].
72
E McKendrick Vicarious liability and independent contractors a re-examination (1990) 53 MLR 770 at 784.
73
Kafagi, above n 67, at [50] (Singh LJ referring to the fact that the tortfeasor-bailiff in this case could turn down work
offered by the respondent company).
74
[2004] EWCA Civ 217.
228 James Brown
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
his Lordship maintained that if the issu e of employment had arisen in relation to a personal injury
action instead of the more abstract question of contract law’–a different result would have ensued.
75
In other words, had Mrs Dacas injured a third party by negligently leaving cleaning equipment in a
dangerous area, it would be a near-certainty that vicarious liability would befall the council, and that
those advancing an alternative submission could look forward to a bad day in court.
76
Again, this
illustrates the normative importance of third-party victims in vicarious liability cases, and it may also ten-
tatively suggest that some judges are of the view that the right to bodily integrity is perhaps deserving of
greater protection than the right not to be unfairly dismissed. Given Dagans comments which suggest
that our lives are divided into economically and socially differentiated segments, and each such transac-
tion of life has some features that are of sufficient normative importance that justifies a distinct legal
treatment
77
this may be a sensible distinction to make.
(c) Formulating a policy-oriented approach to vicarious liability for funded athletes
I have discussed in the previous sect ion that the primacy of control in the context of vicarious liability
is arguably justified in light of its normative significance in relation to third parties. To suggest that
mutuality of obligations is equally as relevant here is, in the words of Posner, to allow that concept
to become unmoored from any plausible goal of employment law.
78
Nevertheless, we might also
identify a second reason for our focus on control in this context: it overlaps with several other theories
of vicarious liability in a way that mutuality and personal performance clearly do not.
79
This pluralistic
point is an important one, as I have demonstrated elsewhere that a determination of vicarious liability
based on multiple converging theories is far more justifiable than a finding based only on one theory.
80
This is predominantly because, as Giliker points out, the oretical analysis can help to aid clarity by
providing some substance to the building blocks of vicarious liability.
81
Consequently, whilst the
overwhelming scholarly and judicial consensus suggests that control alone ought not to be determina-
tive as a test for employer liability,
82
I believe that it could still be viewed as a prominent concern so
long as its overlap with other relevant theories is made clear. This is largely in accordance with
Morgans view, when he suggests that control could still be a highly useful tool in helping us to dis-
tinguish between employees and independent contractors.
83
The most notable overlap here is that between control and the two forms of enterprise liability out-
lined in the introduction. We might recall that the notion of fairness which has recently been her-
alded as the most influential idea [of vicarious liability] in modern times
84
encapsulates the idea
75
Ibid, at [74].
76
Ibid, at [72]. Note also D Cabrelli Employment Law in Context (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 4th edn, 2020) pp 133
134 (arguing that the general trend and reasoning in Dacas was clearly motivated by policy considerations at the expense
of doctrinal coherence).
77
H Dagan Reconstructing American Legal Realism and Rethinking Private Law Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2013) p 37.
78
E Posner The economic basis of the independent contractor/employee distinction (2021) 100 Texas Law Review 353 at 378.
79
Of course, one might make the point that the benefit formulation of enterprise liability overlaps to some extent with
mutuality of obligation. However, it seems to me that benefit is more closely linked to the notion of control than to the con-
cept of mutual obligations. The latter appears to be more concerned with whether there is an obligation to work, rather than
whether this obligation provides a benefit. In this regard, just because mutual obligations exist does not also mean that a
benefit exists (and vice versa). This is illustrated on the facts of both Varnish and OKelly: in both cases, the defendant
was receiving a benefit (explained below in the context of Varnish), but mutuality of obligations was found not to exist in
either scenario.
80
JBrownDeveloping a contextual-pluralist model of vicarious liability (2021) 28 Tort Law Review 123 at 125.
81
P Giliker Rough justice in an unjust world (2002) 65 MLR 269 at 276; P Giliker Vicarious Liability in Tort: A
Comparative Perspective (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010) p 251.
82
Cox v Ministry of Justice [2016] UKSC 10 at [21] per Lord Reed; CCWS, above n 2, at [49] per Lord Phillips; Atiyah,
above n 51, p 16.
83
P Morgan Certainty in vicarious liability: a quest for a chimaera? (2016) 75 Cambridge Law Journal 202 at 203.
84
Armes v Nottinghamshire County Council [2017] UKSC 60 at [67] per Lord Reed.
Legal Studies 229
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
that an employer who benefits from a particular activity ought to simultaneously bear the burdens of
that conduct.
85
According to Flannigan, the notion of benefit is intrinsically linked to the theory of
control, in that a persons ability to benefit in an equity or residual sense normally depends on
whether or not that person controls the performance of the work.
86
Morgan too makes a similar
point when he outlines that [a]cting on behalf of the employer, and control, also link to [the]
wider notion of enterprise liability.
87
Both control and benefit appear to overlap with the concept
of integration, such that the terms control, integration and benefit can often be used interchange-
ably in most instances. Kidner makes the connection between the first two, when he highlights that the
degree of control exercised by the employer may well depend on the degree to which the employee is
integrated into the activities of the enterprise.
88
In this manner, Be ll is correct to illustrate that control
can be (and indeed has been in Tomlinson LJs Court of Appeal judgment in Armes v Nottinghamshire
County Council
89
) accorded indirect relevance by assessing the integration of an activity into the
defendants enterprise.
90
Furthermore, various judges have demonstrated that integration is also
closely interlinked with any benefits enj oyed by an employer. This was explicitly recognised by
Lord Reed in Cox v Ministry of Justice,
91
and Irwin LJ in the Court of Appeal in Barclays similarly
outlined that the tortfeasor in that case was sufficiently integrated into the business activity of the
defendant because his work was primarily done for the benefit o f the bank.
92
Given that control, integration and benefit all appear to be cut from the same cloth, we might
make the following observation: if an individual is subject to strict control by an organisation, it is
likely that they are also integrated into that organisations business activities and providing a benefit
to that entity. It is no surprise, then, that an analysis of fairness appears to justify vicarious liability for
many funded individual athletes. In Varnish, for instance, it was reported that the ultimate goal for
both British Cycling and its athletes was to win medals for the British Team.
93
Given that the benefit
derived from the tortfeasors activities need not necessarily be financial in nature,
94
one may simply
point to the fact that success would reflect well on the institution as one of the benefits received
by British Cycling.
95
However, it is also evident that an NGBs failure to meet their annual medal
and performance targets (as set by UK Sport) will likely lead to savage cuts on the funding offered
to that sport,
96
so it is arguably the case that British Cycling also reap a financial benefit from the high
degree of control that they exercise over their athletes. Moreover, it was also noted in the EAT that the
NGB were able to make use of Varnishs image in connection with the promotion, publicity or explan-
ation of the Podium Programme,
97
again suggesting a profit-making benefit to both British Cycling
and UK Sport.
In addition to fairness, we might also say that control overlaps to a significant extent with the
risk-related formulation of enterprise liability. The inherent link between control and risk is illustrated
once again by Flannigan when he states that the ability to control is what enables the employer to take
risks. When the employer has no control, he is not in a position to apply his risk set to the activity or
85
See generally, J Fleming The Law of Torts (Sydney: LBC Information Services, 9th edn, 1998) p 410.
86
R Flannigan Enterprise control: the servant-independent contractor distinction (1987) 37 University of Toronto Law
Journal 25 at 33.
87
Morgan, above n 69, at 290.
88
Kidner, above n 63, at 62. Similarly, C Witting Modelling organisational vicarious liability (2019) 39 LS 694 at 705 refers
to an employers ability to control as an integration mechanism.
89
[2015] EWCA Civ 1139 at [15].
90
A Bell The liability of local authorities for abuses by foster parents (2018) 34 PN 38 at 40.
91
Cox, above n 82, at [23].
92
[2018] EWCA Civ 1670, at [51][52].
93
Varnish, above n 35, at [80].
94
Cox, above n 82, at [30].
95
Varnish, above n 37, at [47].
96
Varnish, above n 35, at [28]; J Toney Team GB set to scrap medal targets for Tokyo Olympics The Independent 10 June
2021, available at https://www.independent.co.uk/sport/olympics/tokyo-games-2021-great-britain-b1863512.html.
97
Varnish, above n 37, at [5].
230 James Brown
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
operation.
98
This seems applicable to the facts of Varnish, in that we might say that the existence of
the PAA which includes the package of benefits provided by the NGB and the concomitant obliga-
tions imposed on athletes enables (and thus also increases) the risk of injury to others. The extent to
which it is increased, however, perhaps depends on the type of act committed. Given that British
Cycling only exercise control over (and benefit from) certain aspects of Varnishs lif e, it may be
that vicarious liability would only be appropriate for acts intrinsically linked to that control/benefit.
By way of example, we have seen that the NGB were able to exercise significant control over
Varnishs use of social media, such that any tortious comments made by Varnish on Twitter could
be fair game for vicarious liability. Similarly, given that British Cycling reap the (reputational and
financial) benefit of medals from Varnishs performances, any negligent injury she causes during com-
petition should also be susceptible to vicarious liability.
Contrast this with a scenario whereby Varnish assaults her coach in anger after a particularly bad
performance at an event. Given that the NGB allow Varnish to choose her own coach, it is arguably far
less appropriate to impose vicarious liabi lity on British Cycling for this act. In this manner, we might
say that something similar to the harm-within-risk rule from legal causation ought to operate here,
99
with the result that control, benefit and risk all need to overlap to some extent before vicarious liability
is deemed justifiable. This point was recognised by Bell when he suggested that both benefit and risk
must be kept close together if an enterprise theory is to hold.
100
With reference to the facts of Armes,
he further elaborates that the benefit to the council in utilising foster parents in this case was in run-
ning the child welfare system/discharging its duties, so this should then remain the focus of the risk
creation point.
101
An application of vicarious liability to the individual sporting context appears to
further reinforce the need to heed this advice.
With these points in mind, it is useful to step back and consider what lessons we might learn from a
policy-oriented approach to Varnish and, more broadly, what this potentially means for the vicarious
liability of many NGBs. It is arguable that, if we change the facts in Varnish to emphasise the potential
negligence of the claimant (much like Sedley LJ did in Dacas), British Cycling ought to be vicariously
liable for tortious harm caused by Varnish. Under the approach advocated here, control already
established as significant in the ETs judgment would be afforded greater importance, with the
mutuality and personal performance factors (which pointed in the opposite direction to control in
the tribunals decision) concomitantly being downplayed. This analysis is reinforced by the fact that
control overlaps to a significant extent with enterprise liability, and both fairness and risk would seem-
ingly also justify the imposition of vicarious liability for funded athletes in many scenarios. In add-
ition, the existence of funding under both the PAA and APA may also illustrate that the NGB has
deeper pockets than the individual athlete, and that they are also more able to adequately spread
the loss of any damages award.
Now, this is not to say that Varnish was incorrectly decided, and nor does it mean that all funded
athletes should now be classed as employees for the purposes of unfair dismissal. Rather, the policy-
oriented approach advocated here allows us to recognise, as the Supreme Court did in Pimlico
Plumbers Ltd v Smith,
102
that an athlete can be an employee for one purpose, and self-employed
for another. This is important, in that it helps us to avoid those doomsday arguments that are
often associated with the provision of employment rights and benefits to funded athletes.
103
For
instance, it has been estimated that, had Varnish been found an employee of British Cycling or UK
98
Flannigan, above n 86, at 35.
99
This is often also referred to as the loss within the scope of duty rule. See eg T Keren-Paz Liability for consequences,
duty of care and the limited relevance of specific reliance: new insights on Bhamra v Dubb (2016) 32 PN 50.
100
Bell, above n 90, at 41.
101
Ibid.
102
[2018] UKSC 29.
103
See the discussion in C Fursdon et al The Jess Varnish decision why British athletes are still not considered employ-
ees and what it means for athletes and NGBs LawInSport 5 April 2019, available at https://www.lawinsport.com/topics/item/
the-jess-varnish-decision-why-british-athletes-are-still-not-considered-employees-and-what-it-means-for-athletes-and-ngbs.
Legal Studies 231
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Sport, many NGBs would have encountered serious financial difficulties, with one in five British ath-
letes facing a funding cut.
104
2. Beyond funded athletes: viarious liability in other individual sports
In light of the prima facie case for the vicarious liability of funded athletes, we might take this analysis
a step further and question whether a similar determination could equally apply to other professiona-
lised individual sports where funding is absent. In particular, this requires us to examine whether the
theoretical and contextual arguments applicable to funded athletes are equally as strong when applied
to non-funded athletes. At first glance, the answer appears to be no. A simple deep pockets analysis,
for instance, suggests that there is no need for vicarious liability at all in this scenario, as non-funded
professional athletes are likely to be solvent and able to meet a significant damages award themselves.
Consequently, when we see various tempestuous tennis stars engaging in potentially harm-causing
activities such as Novak Djokovic negligently hitting a line judge with a tennis ball at the 2020
US Open;
105
Nick Kyrgios hurling his racket into the crowd at Wimbledon in 2015;
106
David
Nalbandian wounding a line umpire after kicking out at an advertising board in 2012;
107
and Juan
Ignacio Chela spitting at his opponent Lleyton Hewitt in 2005
108
we might justifiably conclude
that there is no need to consider the potential liability of a governing body at all in these scenarios.
After all, both corrective justice and deterrence seem to point towards imposing direct liability on
the athletes, and the main compensation rationale for vicarious liability largely falls away when we
consider the lucrative career of a professional tennis player.
However, this analysis may be criticised as under-inclusive. Imposing direct liability on the tortfea-
sor may only be a viable option for those athletes at the very apex of the sport who regularly compete
for the biggest prizes in tennis. In contrast, a negligence claim against those athletes lower down the
pecking order is far less feasible. In fact, according to a 2013 study by the International Tennis
Federation (ITF), around 45% of the 13,736 professional tennis players earned nothing from the
sport in that year,
109
and athletes placed outside of the top 200 ranking spots were unlikely to earn
more than £40,000 in prize money over the course of those 12 months.
110
As such, when we hear
of stories such as those involving former world number 248 Harmony Tan who accused a similar-
ranked opponent of intentionally hitting her in the eye with a tennis ball during an ITF event
111
we
might conclude that the vicarious liability of the relevant tennis governing body is much more
104
Russell and Nicholson, above n 27. Note also the argument made by Thomas Linden QC (the lawyer for British
Cycling), who suggested that a judgment for Varnish would have been equivalent to the skies falling in for UK NGBs.
See T Cary Jess Varnish unlikely to hear outcome of tribunal for at least four weeks The Telegraph 18 May 2020, available
at https://www.telegraph.co.uk/cycling/2020/05/18/jess-varnish-unlikely-hear-outcome-tribunal-appeal-least-four/.
105
Novak Djokovic apologises after hitting line judge with ball at US Open BBC News 7 September 2020, available at
https://www.bbc.com/sport/tennis/54052345. For a previously similar incident involving the Canadian player Denis
Shapovalov, see Denis Shapovalov fined $7000 for smashing ball in tennis umpireseye The Guardian 6 February 2017,
available at https://www.theguardian.com/sport/2017/feb/06/denis-shapovalov-fined-smashing-ball-tennis-umpire-eye.
106
E Addley Nick Kyrgios bounces racket into crowd during tantrum at Wimbledon The Guardian 3 July 2015, available
at https://www.theguardian.com/sport/2015/jul/03/kyrgios-bounces-racket-spectators-tantrum-wimbledon.
107
D Ornstein David Nalbandian disqualified from Queens final after kick BBC News 18 June 2012, available at https://
www.bbc.co.uk/sport/tennis/18491229.
108
See eg C Seddell The 13 nastiest on-court spats in tennis history Bleacher Report 26 October 2011, available at https://
bleacherreport.com/articles/908424-13-nastiest-on-court-spats-in-tennis-history-video (also reporting other various infam-
ous tennis assaults, such as Stefan Koubek choking Daniel Koellerer at an ATP event in 2010).
109
Tennis match-fixing a secret on the tour everybody knows”’ BBC News 19 January 2016, available at https://www.bbc.
co.uk/sport/tennis/35356550.
110
Tennis match-fixing allegations explained BBC News 18 January 2016, available at https://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-
35343063.
111
French player accuses opponent of intentionally hitting her in the eye with ball Tennis World 13 January 2020, avail-
able at https://www.tennisworldusa.org/tennis/news/Tennis_Stories/82713/french-player-accuses-opponent-of-intentionally-
hitting-her-in-the-eye-with-ball/. Unfortunately, this is a rather common practice amongst tennis players. See eg Nick
232 James Brown
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
appropriate here. This is reinforced by the healthy financial status of many organisations that seek to
regulate their respective sports. One example is that of the PGA Tour in golf. Despite its status as a
non-profit organisation, the PGA Tour actually boasts an annual revenue in excess of US$1 billion.
112
This, it is suggested, feeds into a number of other relevant points here.
First, the PGA Tour is actually a competition organiser (rather than an NGB),
113
and it may be that
organisers of sports competitions could be just as susceptible to vicarious liability as governing bod-
ies.
114
Given that control over non-funded athletes is often exercised simultaneously by varying bodies,
it might be that dual vicarious liability is sometimes appropriate in this context.
115
This form of liabil-
ity allows courts to find multiple employers strictly liable for the tort of an employee, and this seems to
be an inherently useful tool for recognising that, in many scenarios, different employers may well pos-
sess different levels of responsibility according to the degree of control they enjoy.
116
Such dual liabil-
ity could be particularly useful in sports such as boxing, where the so-called alphabet soup of
sanctioning organisations which includes four different bodies overseeing six world champions in
each of 17 different weight categories undoubtedly complexifies the analysis.
117
Secondly, tennis is clearly not the only sport in which it might be appropriate to hold a regulator
vicariously liable, and it is for such reasons that I examine how this analysis might also be applied to
the sport of golf. The potential for injury here is obvious, particularly to spectators. This is evidenced
by the recent incident at the 2018 Ryder Cup, where an onlooker was blinded in one eye after being hit
by Brooks Koepkas wayward shot.
118
Whilst there was no evidence that Koepka was negligent in his
drive, it would not be difficult to imagine following the line of reckless duffers cases such as Pearson
v Lightning
119
and Phee v Gordon
120
a slightly different scenario in which negligence could be estab-
lished. For instance, had it been established that Koepka was intoxicated when he took the shot
much like former professional golfer Rocco Mediate, who admitted that drinking whilst on PGA
Tour courses was normal for him
121
it may have been justifiable to hold the organisation respon-
sible for this harm.
Third, in examining the potential scope of vicarious liability in these sports, it must be highlighted
that my analysis is consistent with the Supreme Courts recent clarification of control in CCWS. There,
Lord Phillips highlighted that control is now more about whether an employer can direct what an
employee does (rather than simply how he does it).
122
As such, the exercise conducted here is similar
to that carried out by Morgan under his dual axis approach to employer liability.
123
On this basis, he
highlights various factors that go towards assessing both an employers day to day control and an
employees discretion in role. These include, for instance, prescription of: working hours and
Kyrgios wanted to hit Rafael Nadal with shot at Wimbledon BBC News 4 July 2019, available at https://www.bbc.co.uk/
sport/tennis/48877052.
112
M Burke The PGA Tour: a not-for-profit money machine Forbes 8 May 2013, available at https://www.forbes.com/
sites/monteburke/2013/05/08/the-pga-tour-a-not-for-profit-money-machine/#c21746d57339.
113
The governance of golf is instead left to the United States Golf Association (USGA) for US golf, and to The R&A for
every other country.
114
This accords with the analysis found in Gardiner et al, above n 15, p 395 (where it is highlighted that, in German law, a
competition organiser or a sponsor could be considered an employer).
115
For confirmation of this possibility, see Viasystems (Tyneside) Ltd v Thermal Transfer (Northern) Ltd [2005] EWCA Civ
1151.
116
D Brodie The enterprise and the borrowed worker (2006) 35 Industrial Law Journal 87 at 89.
117
J Anderson The Legality of Boxing: A Punch Drunk Love? (Abingdon: Routledge, 2006) pp 6570.
118
Ryder Cup: spectator blinded in one eye says she could have died on golf course BBC News 3 October 2018, available at
https://www.bbc.co.uk/sport/golf/45734449.
119
[1998] EWCA Civ 591.
120
[2011] CSOH 181.
121
M Bonesteel Now sober, pro golfer Rocco Mediate admits to drinking while playing PGA Tour events The Washington
Post 7 February 2019, available at https://www.washingtonpost.com/sports/2019/02/07/now-sober-pro-golfer-rocco-mediate-
admits-drinking-while-playing-pga-tour-events/.
122
CCWS, above n 2, at [36] per Lord Phillips.
123
P Morgan Recasting vicarious liability (2012) 71 Cambridge Law Journal 615 at 642643.
Legal Studies 233
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
location; uniforms; disciplinary systems; the use of certain methods and equipment; and when breaks
can be taken. An application of these factors to governing bodies and competition organisers in pro-
fessional tennis and golf highlights both their control over, and benefit from, the athletes competing
under their auspices, and this suggests that vicarious liability may sometimes be appropriate even for
non-funded athletes. This conclusion is also consistent with Dabschecks analysis, as he highlights how
a more nuanced assessment of the restrictions imposed upon professional jockeys such as limited
control over their own attire, fitness levels, use of intellectual property rights and adherence to gam-
bling and drug codes suggests that they should be properly regarded as employees and not inde-
pendent contractors.
124
Interestingly, this may have meant that, had negligence been established in
the seminal sports torts case of Caldwell v Maguire and Fitzgerald (which involved allegedly careless
riding by a professional jockey),
125
the British Horseracing Authority could have been held vicariously
liable for this injury.
Fourth, it must be conceded that not all scholars would agree with utilising vicarious liability to
hold NGBs and competition organisers responsible for harmful conduct. Some commentators
(such as Gray, for instance) would likely believe that it is more appropriate to hold such organisations
directly liable in negligence.
126
Given the need to prove fault for such an action, however, this may not
be an adequate solution for those who are convinced by my pro-liability stance in this context.
Consider, for instance, the aforementioned example involving Rocco Mediate: the PGA Tour would
likely only be liable in negligence for this harm if it could be shown that they were aware of the tort-
feasors inebriated state, but failed to take action. In contrast, (strict) vicarious liability would still apply
in such a scenario, irrespective of the organisations knowledge or any prior training they o ffered to the
athlete.
Likewise, others may suggest that a non-delegable duty an exceptional no-fault based form of
primary liability could be placed on sporting bodies to ensure that reasonable care is taken by par-
ticipants in individual sports.
127
Now, whilst I believe that the non-delegable duty might be able to
work alongside a pleading of vicarious liability (as occurred in a number of recent dental negligence
cases),
128
the concept is not sufficiently developed or determinate enough, in my opinion, to com-
pletely replace a vicarious liability claim. This is evidenced by the vast uncertainty that continues to
exist in relation to Lord Sumptions guidance on non-delegable duties in Woodland v Essex County
Council.
129
Although his guidance was never meant to be set in stone,
130
it remains unclear as to
whether any of the tests outlined by Lord Sumption would be satisfied in relation to the individual
sports context.
131
In this light, Giliker concludes that vicarious liability remains the stronger and
124
B Dabscheck Sweated labour, literally speaking: the case of Australian jockeys in Y Lee and R Fort (eds) The Sports
Business in the Pacific Rim: Economic and Policy (New York: Springer, 2014) pp 322325.
125
[2001] EWCA Civ 1054.
126
Gray, above n 52, pp 272273.
127
C Beuermann Reconceptualising Strict Liability for the Tort of Another (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2019); P Watts The
travails of vicarious liability (2019) 135 Law Quarterly Review 7 at 11.
128
Ramdhean v Agedo [2020] 1 WLUK 406; Breakingbury v Croad (19 April 2021, unreported), County Court (Cardiff).
129
[2013] UKSC 66 at [23]. Lord Sumption outlined that non-delegable duties can be characterised by five defining fea-
tures: (i) the claimant is especially vulnerable or dependent; (ii) there is an antecedent relationship between the claimant and
defendant (which involves the latter exercising custody, care or charge over the former), and from which it is possible to
impute a positive duty to protect the claimant from harm; (iii) the claimant cannot control how the defendant performs
those obligations; (iv) the defendant delegates a function which is integral to the duty he assumes towards the claimant;
and (v) this function was performed negligently by the third party.
130
Ibid, at [38] per Baroness Hale.
131
To take a few examples, it is unclear whether an individual athlete could be meaningfully classed as vulnerable for the
purposes of the first test. If so, is it also accurate to maintain that they are in the custody, care or charge of an NGB? And
even if one could establish this requirement in relation to individual participants, it is doubtful that a spectator injured by a
wayward golf shot could equally be classed as dependent on the governing body. Finally, there is arguably vast uncertainty as
to what functions are inherent to an NGBs duties. See, for instance, P Giliker, Non-delegable duties and institutional liabil-
ity for the negligence of hospital staff: fair, just and reasonable? (2017) 33 PN 109 at 120.
234 James Brown
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
more predictable option for claimants,
132
and it is perhaps for such reasons that the non-delegable
duty was not raised at all in the recent Barclays litigation.
Finally, it may be that the discussion here could lead some NGBs to seri ously consider imposing an
obligation upon all athletes in their sport to take out appropriate liability insurance. Indeed, if an ath-
lete is insured against any negligent harm he causes, the injured party is less likely to feel the need to
test the vicarious liability of an NGB in a court of law.
133
The practicality of this solution is, however,
largely dependent on two factors: the type of sport; and the extent of control exercised by the govern-
ing body. For some sports, such as tennis and golf, compulsory liability insurance for every athlete
might be a useful development for the governing bodies to consider, particularly in light of the poten-
tial for injury in these sports and the stringent regulation that these athletes are subjected to. For other
regulators, such as the World Darts Federation (WDF), this suggestion may be a rather pointless one.
Not only is darts a sport in which injuries hardly ever occur, but the WDF also take a relatively lenient
approach to the obligations of their players, and thus do not really possess the necessary degree of
control over their athletes to justify vicarious liability.
134
However, even if there are NGBs that wish
to mandate liability insurance for all participants, some burning questions remain: would such a devel-
opment lead to the end of pro-am tournaments, where professio nal and amateur athletes compete
together in a single event? It is one thing to require a professional athlete to take out appropriate liability
insurance, but it is another thing entirely to require an amateur player to do so, particularly considering
the likelihood that they may not be able to afford (or at least justify the cost of) such insurance. Likewise,
we might also ponder whether insurers would be willing to provide such cover at all. Boyes makes the
point that, in light of the increasing wealth of many top athletes, insurers may refuse to cover those who
play high-value opponents.
135
After all (and to slightly modify a concern first raised by Boyes), who
really wants to insure the person who might blind Rafael Nadal or Jordan Spieth?
(a) Tennis
Professional tennis is governed by a number of bodies, one of which is the aforementioned ITF.
136
The
ITF operates as the world governing body of tennis, with responsibilities including the enforcement of
the Rules of Tennis and the organisation of various tournaments (such as the four Grand Slam tour-
naments, the international Davis Cup and Fed Cup, and the lower-rung ITF Mens and Womens
World Tennis Tours). The Association of Tennis Professionals (ATP) which operates several com-
petitions under the ATP Tour and ATP Challenger Tour acts as the governing body for mens tennis,
whilst the Womens Tennis Association (WTA) acts as the global governing body for womens tennis.
Although Gibson argues that the economi c independence of professional tennis players means that no
governing body is exercising control over them,
137
a brief perusal of the ITF, Grand Slam and ATP
rulebooks suggest that this analysis is perhaps too simplistic. For example, with regard to the
132
Giliker, above n 5, at 71.
133
Somewhat paradoxically, this might mean that the exercise of even greater control over athletes could make NGBs less
likely to be held vicariously liable. However, even if the injured party was fully compensated by the tortfeasors liability insur-
ance, the vicarious liability of an NGB may still be tested if the insurer exercises their rights of subrogation.
134
World Darts Federation Playing and tournament rules available at https://dartswdf.com/rules. A glance at the (rela-
tively brief) rules imposed by the WDF highlights that many obligations that are commonplace in other sports such as
mandatory attendance at post-match conferences are absent here. This is presumably because they are not as commercially
minded as many other NGBs.
135
S Boyes Compensate footballers after injury, but dont let insurance costs ruin the game The Conversation 28 February
2014, available at https://theconversation.com/compensate-footballers-after-injury-but-dont-let-insurance-costs-ruin-the-
game-23797.
136
To clarify, the analysis here is limited to those tournaments held in the UK (the most notable of which being
Wimbledon, but also including other events such as the Nitto ATP Finals, the Queens Club Championship and the
Eastbourne International). However, it may be that the present analysis could prove persuasive in other jurisdictions
where professional tennis events are commonly held, such as in France, Australia and the USA.
137
A Gibson Sports Law in Australia (Alphen aan den Rijn: Kluwer, 2017) paras [173][174].
Legal Studies 235
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
provisions laid down by the ITF and the Grand Slam Board (GSB), the rules outline that both bodies
can exercise control over: the discipline of athletes found guilty of doping or corruption;
138
the time
and location of matches;
139
the audible and visible actions of the athletes (including any unsports-
manlike conduct);
140
when athletes can take a break during a match;
141
and the prompt attendance
at post-match media conferences.
142
This latter requirement sparked international outrage during the 2021 French Open, when the for-
mer world number one Naomi Osaka cited mental health issues for her refusal to attend a post-match
press conference.
143
She was later fined US$15,000 for the failure to honour this obligation, and one
suspects that this was largely because the governing bodies in tennis stood to benefit from her inter-
action with the media. As the Grand Slam rulebook highlights, media appearances by the top stars
provides valuable exposure to the media and fans, and this in turn helps to drive engageme nt
with the sport.
144
One can see, therefore, parallels with respect to funded athletes like Varnish, as gov-
erning bodies here are enjoying a similar level of control over, and benefit from, non-funded athletes
too. This is reinforced by other stringent regulatory policies that are imposed by the ITF and GSB on
professional tennis players, such as: restrictions on their participation in other events;
145
the degree to
which they can promote their own sponsors;
146
and the close regulation of what attire and equipment
is appropriate to wear and use during competition. In particular, participants competing at
Wimbledon are famously obliged to wear white clothing,
147
and there are comprehensive regulations
on what footwear is acceptable for different types of court.
148
Likewise, the ATP rulebook exhibits many similar limits on an athletes discretion, both on and off
the court. In relation to on-court restrictions, the ATP can impose financial penalties on so-called
commitment players’–those ranked in the top 30 of the ATPs official rankings who fail to par-
ticipate in a certain number of competitions.
149
The rationale behind such a rule is, presumably,
that the ATP want to accrue the financial and promotional benefits of the top stars regularly compet-
ing under their brand. Regarding the off-field control of professional tennis players, it is noteworthy
that the ATP currently operate a so-called STARS program.
150
This initiative, which was introduced
138
International Tennis Integrity Agency Tennis anti-corruption program (2022) available at https://www.itftennis.com/
media/4483/2022-tennis-anti-corruption-program-english.pdf.
139
According to International Tennis Federation 2022 mens and womens ITF world tennis tour regulations available at
https://www.itftennis.com/media/7286/2022-itf-world-tennis-tour-regulations.pdf at 171 (hereafter ITF World Tennis Tour);
Grand Slam Board 2022 official Grand Slam rulebook available at https://www.itftennis.com/media/5986/grand-slam-rule-
book-2022-f-2.pdf at 39 (hereafter Grand Slam Rulebook), a player may be fined, respectively, US$50 or US$10,000 if they are
not ready to play when their match is called.
140
ITF World Tennis Tour at 177179; Grand Slam Rulebook at 4649.
141
ITF World Tennis Tour at 136; Grand Slam Rulebook at 2122 (highlighting that participants are allowed to leave the
court for a reasonable time for a toilet break once during a best-of-three sets match).
142
Athletes must attend their post-match media conference within a reasonable time (usually 60 minutes) of the conclu-
sion of each match: see ITF World Tennis Tour at 180; Grand Slam Rulebook at 45.
143
TCarayolNaomi Osaka will not speak to French Open press due to mental health impact The Guardian 27 May 2021,
available at https://www.theguardian.com/sport/2021/may/27/naomi-osaka-will-not-speak-to-french-open-press-mental-health-
tennis.
144
Grand Slam Rulebook at 45.
145
ITF World Tennis Tour at 161163; Grand Slam Rulebook at 37.
146
ITF World Tennis Tour at 172175; Grand Slam Rulebook at 4143.
147
Grand Slam Rulebook at 41. See also All England Lawn Tennis Club Clothing and equipment available at https://www.
wimbledon.com/en_GB/about_wimbledon/clothing_and_equipment.html.
148
ITF World Tennis Tour at 171172; Grand Slam Rulebook at 3941.
149
Association of Tennis Professionals, 2022 ATP official rulebook available at https://www.atptour.com/en/corporate/
rulebook,at1013 (hereafter ATP Rulebook).
150
See also (ibid, at 1415) the requirement that all players are to grant and assign to ATP the right in perpetuity to record
in tangible form and to allow ATP to use their name, performance, likeness, voice, and biography, in any and all media
solely for purposes of advertising and promoting [the] ATP Tour. Mixed Martial Arts fighters competing in the UFC are also
subject to similar limitations on the use of their intellectual property rights: see D Pannett Collective bargaining in sport:
challenges and benefits (2015) 4 UCL Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 189 at 202.
236 James Brown
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
in an effort to exploit the popularity of athletes through sponsorships and media,
151
mandates that
[a]ll players competing in the main draw of any ATP Tour tournament will be required, if asked, to
participate in ATP sponsored activities.
152
Each player is required to dedicate up to two hours per
week to the program, as well as participating in up to two activity days for promotional purposes
(which may even take place outside of an ATP Tour tournament week and/or location).
153
Given
that such activities sometimes place athletes in a position of power by working with children,
154
it
could certainly be argued that, if a tennis player sexually abused a child as a result of his engagement
with this program, the ATP ought to be vicariously liable for this act. This is consistent not only with
case law demonstrating that the conferral of power on an employee strengthens the argument for
imposing vicarious liability,
155
but also with the so-called harm-within-risk rule posited above.
Unlike an on-court injury caused during a training session or warm-up (which the ATP
exercise very little control over and reap no b enefit from),
156
attendance at STARS events is something
that the ATP explicitly mandate and profit from. In this light, we could say that the risk of off-court
sexual abuse at a promotional event is within the scope of the governing bodys relevant control/
integration.
(b) Golf
Similar themes evident in tennis can also be identified in the context of professional golf. For instance,
the aforementioned PGA Tour, which identifies itself as the worlds premier membership organiza-
tion for touring professional golfers,
157
is able to exert a significant degree of control over those par-
ticipating in their events. According to its most recently published handbook covering the 201920
season, the competition organiser is able to regulate a players use of mobile devices and social
media throughout the tour,
158
as well as impose strict limitations on any sponsorships and equipment
deemed contrary to the spirit of golf.
159
As evidenced by PGA Tour Inc v Martin,
160
this even extends
to the PGA Tours attempts to control whether certain disabled competitors are permitted to use golf
carts to traverse the course (which, according to some, looked lousy on television).
161
A professional
golfers discretion in role is also inhibited by strict rules requiring them to maintain a certain pace of
play whilst out on the green,
162
as well as further restrictions on their signing of autographs and
151
A Sorrentini and T Pianese The relationships among stakeholders in the organization of mens professional tennis
events (2011) 3 Global Business and Management Research 141 at 149.
152
ATP Rulebook at 15.
153
Ibid, at 1516.
154
See eg Flashback: successful kids day supports more than 400 children in Budapest ATP Tour 20 April 2020, available
at https://www.atptour.com/en/news/budapest-2018-charity-event.
155
Bazley v Curry [1999] 2 SCR at [41][44] per McLachlin J; The Trustees of the Barry Congregation of Jehovahs Witnesses
v BXB [2021] EWCA Civ 356 at [95] per Males LJ.
156
The lack of control over training and tactics is, for some scholars, crucial to the finding that a tennis player ought to be
viewed as an independent contractor. See C Flake Getting to deuce: professional tennis and the need for expanding coverage
of federal antidiscrimination laws (2014) 16 Texas Review of Entertainment and Sports Law 51 at 6263; A Gibson The
Association of Tennis Professionals: from player association to governing body (2010) 10 Journal of Applied Business
and Economics 23; D Healey Sport and the Law (Sydney: UNSW Press, 2009) pp 5960.
157
See https://www.pgatour.com/company/aboutus.html.
158
PGA Tour Player handbook and tournament regulations: 201920 available at https://qualifying.pgatourhq.com/static-
assets/uploads/2019-2020-pga-tour-handbook--regs-09_10_19.pdf,at7475 (hereafter PGA Tour Handbook).
159
Ibid, at 7578 (for sponsorship limitations); at 60 (for equipment restrictions). See also the highly technical and
in-depth equipment rules produced by The R&A and USGA, available at https://www.randa.org/en/equipment-rules.
160
532 US 661 (2001).
161
R Sandomir Golf; a by-the-book defence versus Martins reality New York Times 8 February 1998, available at https://
www.nytimes.com/1998/02/08/sports/golf-a-by-the-book-defense-versus-martin-s-reality.html.
162
PGA Tour Handbook at 6770; The R&A Pace of play manual available at https://www.randa.org/en/rules/pace-of-
play. See also Plan to tackle slow play comes into effect European Tour 14 January 2020, available at https://www.european-
tour.com/european-tour/news/articles/detail/plan-to-tackle-slow-play-comes-into-effect/.
Legal Studies 237
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
consumption of alcohol during competitions.
163
This latter provision suggests that the PGA Tour
ought, in fact, to be held vicariously liable for any injury caused due to the negligent swing of an
intoxicated golfer, as the control exercised by the organisation over this conduct is closely related
to the relevant risk of harm.
Of course, this is not to say that professional golfers do not retain some form of control over their
activities. They are able to choose both their own caddy and which tournaments they wish to enter, but
even here the PGA Tour seem to have the last word. The organisation gives the final approval on each
caddy,
164
and members of the tour must compete in at least 25 events over the course of the year or
else risk a major fine or suspension.
165
Much like with the obligation foisted upon commitment
players by the ATP, we could say that this requirement to play a certain number of games is especially
important for vicarious liability purposes, as the governing bodies and competition organisers are
explicitly influencing the level of risk posed by their athletes. As such, Sharpe is seemingly correct
to argue that these control mechanisms tend to show an employer-employee relationship between
the PGA Tour and its golfers.
166
Given that this comment was made for the purposes of employment
and disability law, we could say that her argument is further strengthened when it is applied to the
context of vicarious liability (becaus e, as explained above, the normative importance of control is
even more significant in this context).
A similar state of affairs is also identifiable in womens golf, where the Ladies Professional Golf
Association (LPGA) and its concomitant LPGA Tour operates in a functionally similar manner
to its male counterpart. One of the LPGAs more interesting policies for our purposes arose in
August 2008, when the organisation attempted to enforce a new rule mandating that all participants
on the tour speak English during pro-am events and when interacting with the media.
167
The pur-
ported reason for this rule was to please corporate sponsors and to maximize the marketability of
its players in an attempt to improve the popularity of the tour.
168
Although the LPGA later back-
tracked on this policy (albeit with a version of the rule still remaining an option),
169
this example
shows that, by acceding to these demands, foreign women golfers were clearly asked to carry on an
activity that constituted an integral part of the business activities of the LPGA, and were doing so
for its benefit.
170
Lloyd persuasively argues that, [b]y controlling the language that an LPGA player
must speak, the LPGA is effectively exerting one of the most stifling and limited forms of employer
control.
171
In this light, and as he further elaborates, the courts must take a hard look at whether
a professional golfer is really an independent contractor when the tour mandates the language that
she must speak during the course of her membership on the tour.
172
Conclusion
The adoption of a more contextual, policy-sensitive approach to an individuals employment status
reveals that many NGBs and competition organ isers ought to be held vicariously liable for tortious
163
PGA Tour Handbook at 66, 71.
164
T Sharpe Caseys case: taking a slice out of the PGA Tours no-cart policy (1999) 26 Florida State University Law
Review 783 at 802.
165
See eg B Harig Jordan Spieth must qualify for tour championship to avoid PGA sanctions ESPN 9 September 2018,
available at https://www.espn.co.uk/golf/story/_/id/24618330/jordan-spieth-faces-fine-suspension-misses-minimum-num-
ber-pga-tour-events.
166
Sharpe, above n 164, at 805.
167
J Newport How the LPGA bungled on English Wall Street Journal 13 September 2008, available at https://www.wsj.
com/articles/SB122125269803829639 .
168
A Lloyd Youre next on the tee, just remember to speak English! Could the LPGA really force players to learn and speak
English? (2009) 9 Virginia Sports & Entertainment Law Journal 181 at 182, 189.
169
S Patel Inclusion and Exclusion in Competitive Sport (London: Routledge, 2015) p 144.
170
Cox, above n 82, at [24] per Lord Reed. See also Martin, above n 160, at 669.
171
Lloyd, above n 168, at 189.
172
Ibid, at 189190.
238 James Brown
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press
behaviour committed by athletes that compete under their auspices. This is a novel claim that has yet
to be made in the scant literature on vicarious liability in sport. In relation to funded athletes in indi-
vidual sports, it was maintained that the recent case of Varnish may provide an instructive roadmap
for the implementation of such a policy-oriented approach. It was highlighted that certain factors
prominent in employment law such as mutuality of obligations and personal performance
ought to be downplayed when dealing with the issue of vicarious liability for the purposes of tort
law. Conversely, this paper suggested that the notion of control ought to be prioritised in this context,
as this theory arguably has a much stronger moral and normative impact on third parties.
As a result of this discussion, a number of important claims were made. First, it was observed that
some athletes could be classed as employees for one purpose, but independent contractors for others.
This is largely in accordance with recent case law in this area, and it is an eminently sensible approach
insofar as it recognises the different policy considerations that underpin an unfair dismissal and vic-
arious liability claim. Secondly, and with reference to the facts of Varnish, it was also highlighted that
control, benefit and risk may all need to overlap to a significant extent in order to produce a harmo-
nious and logically consistent theory of enterprise liability. Given that enterprise liability has recently
been touted as the strongest and most convincing rationale for vicarious liability, this is an important
theoretical clarification that ought to be made in the law. Consequently, this is merely one example of
how a sport-specific analysis of vicarious liability could help to teach us some broader lessons about
the doctrine more generally.
Finally, this paper also established that it may be appropriate to impose vicarious liability on NGBs
and competition organisers for the tortious actions of non-funded professional athletes too. This was
illustrated most prominently with reference to the sports of tennis and golf. A brief perusal of the
overly intrusive regulatory measures that are evident in the rulebooks of the se sports demonstrates
that it would certainly be feasible to impose vicarious liability on bodies such as the ATP and the
PGA Tour. In this regard, and on a brief concluding note, it may be wise to end this paper with
the following salutary warning: if sporting governing bodies and competition organisers wish to
avoid the prospect of being held vicariously liable for the tortious behaviour of their athletes, they
ought to seriously consider reducing the extent of some of their on-field and off-field regulatory
policies.
Cite this article: Brown J (2023). The vicarious liability of sports governing bodies and competition organisers. Legal Studies
43, 221239. https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34
Legal Studies 239
https://doi.org/10.1017/lst.2022.34 Published online by Cambridge University Press